A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value. Группа авторов
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value - Группа авторов страница 37
———. The Hidden Half, 2001.
———. The Fifth Reaction, 2003.
———. Cease Fire, 2006.
———. Cease Fire 2, 2014.
Ohanian, Ovanes. Abi and Rabi,1930.
———. Haji Aqa, the Movie Actor, 1933.
Panahi, Jafar. Crimson Gold, 2003.
Pontecorvo, Gillo. The Battle of Algiers, 1966.
Rustayi, Saeed. Just 6.5/Metri Shehsho Nim, 2019.
Sehat, Soroush. Dance with Me, 2019.
Sepanta, Abdol Hossein and Ardeshir Irani. The Lor Girl, 1933.
———. Ferdowsi, 1934.
———. Shirin and Farhad, 1934.
———. Black Eyes, 1936.
———. Leyli va Majnun, 1937.
Zandi Haghighi, Mona. African Violet, 2019.
3 Appreciating Nature through Film A Defense of Mediated Appreciation
Glenn Parsons
Although the nature film is a major film genre, philosophers writing about the aesthetics of nature have paid scant attention to it.1 One searches largely in vain for mentions of film in the literature; in contrast, representations of nature in other art forms, such as landscape painting and photography, have received extensive discussion.
One explanation for this oddity might be that nature film is of scientific, rather than aesthetic, interest. But this is manifestly false: as any viewer of these films knows, they are highly aestheticized, and frequently boast of revealing to viewers, in rich, high-definition experience, the beauty of the natural world. While it is true that much nature film also aspires to scientific interest, this can hardly explain the neglect of the genre, since many writers on the aesthetics of nature view science as directly relevant to the aesthetic appreciation of nature.2
A different explanation would point to the problematic history of nature film itself. Even within film studies, the genre receives relatively little attention, and has several problematic features. One is its reputation for deception. The most egregious examples involve outright misrepresentation of scientific fact, as in the infamous scene in Disney’s White Wilderness (1958) that purports to show lemmings marching off a cliff, when in fact the filmmakers were heaving them over it. More commonplace is the use of staging and editing techniques to present what appears to be natural, but is actually not, as when the BBC cut zoo footage of polar bear cubs into a story about Arctic polar bears in Frozen Planet (2011).3
Another worry about nature film is its ideological character. This worry is obviously related to the first one: by misrepresenting nature, or being highly selective in presenting it, Disney’s early nature films were, arguably, more concerned with reinforcing American social norms than depicting nature (Mitman 1999; Bousé 2000; MacDonald 2017). And finally, there have long been ethical worries about nature film, relating to its misrepresentation of fact, the abuse of animals, and negative effects on environmental attitudes (Bousé 2000; Benedictus 2016). Regarding the latter, nature film has even been derided as “ecoporn,” a genre that “satiates by providing objects for fantasy without making uncomfortable demands on the subject” (Millet 2004; Welling 2009).
While these are all real issues with nature film, I doubt that they fully explain its almost complete neglect in the aesthetics of nature, for these are mainly contingent problems with particular instances, and hardly impugn the genre per se. The 2019 Netflix series Our Planet, for example, was praised for incorporating a much more pervasive and accurate narrative of human environmental impact than any previous nature film. It also dedicated an entire episode to documenting the various stages of the filming and production process.
I believe there is a deeper explanation, which is that, in nature aesthetics, there has been a long-standing undercurrent of suspicion, not to say hostility, toward mediated appreciation in general. By “mediated appreciation” of nature, I mean appreciation that occurs not through direct or “in person” perception of nature, but through experience of a representation of nature. In this paper, I examine this opposition and argue that, while mediated appreciation of nature does involve certain dangers, these have largely been exaggerated, and have led to an unfortunate neglect of film by nature aesthetics. Furthermore, I’ll argue that considering film in fact helps to defuse these very worries about mediated appreciation. This is important, because mediated appreciation constitutes an important and under-studied dimension of the aesthetic appreciation of nature. Furthermore, film’s capacity to mediate nature appreciation reveals an important aspect of its role as a public artform: by reshaping our relationship to natural beauty, film has the potential to alter both the public’s understanding of environmental value and its behavior with respect to the environment.
Mediated Appreciation
To begin, let me further explain the aforementioned notion of mediated appreciation.4 This is familiar to all of us from our experience with everyday photographs: by looking at a photograph, it seems that we can appreciate the subject of the photograph. For example, we can appreciate Cary Grant’s handsome features through looking at certain photographs of him. It may be true that these photographs themselves are nice-looking images, but it’s also true that Grant, the man, was nice-looking, and though you may never have met him, you can come to that assessment by looking at photos of him. Such aesthetic appreciation of Grant’s features is mediated by—it takes place through—viewing these images. Let us say that a representation of an object that, through our experience of it, allows us to thereby appreciate that object is appreciatively apt for it. Being appreciatively apt, we should note, is a matter of degree: a color photo of Grant would be more appreciatively apt for his looks than a black and white one.5
That photographs of people and everyday objects can be appreciatively apt seems clear. But what about representations of other things? Consider art: just as we use photographs to appreciate people’s looks, so we also use them to appreciate works of art. A photograph of Degas’ L’Etoile is different from, and does not fully substitute for, the artwork in the Louvre: the size is obviously different, for example; the texture of the paint and the brushstrokes may not be evident in the photograph; and the glossy sheen of a photographic reproduction is not a property of the original canvas. Nonetheless, reproductions do present to us many of the work’s features, such as the composition of shapes and colors on the canvas, and we can appreciate the work’s aesthetic achievement, to some degree, on that basis. Another familiar example of appreciating art in a mediated way is listening to a recording of a live vocal performance: the recording presents to us some of the relevant qualities of the performance, and thereby allows us to appreciate it (again, to some degree) without directly perceiving it (Semczyszyn 2013b).
These cases of mediated appreciation of artworks are familiar and commonplace, and they do play an important role in our appreciation of art. Our culture’s aesthetic appreciation of painting would be very different, were it not for the existence of photographic reproduction. Nonetheless, mediated appreciation seems to have only a secondary importance in the appreciation of art. Direct perceptual experience