A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value - Группа авторов страница 38

A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

convenience, and themselves raising no theoretical puzzles.

      In the case of mediated appreciation of nature, however, we find matters somewhat inverted. Here mediated experience plays a much more central role than it does in our appreciation of art: most of us have never seen, or will ever see, a polar bear in its Arctic habitat, the Great Barrier Reef, or a Sahara desert landscape. If we have any aesthetic access to these at all, it is an access mediated via representations such as photos, paintings, film, and literary narratives. Indeed, there are some parts of nature that can only be appreciated through representations, for practical or prudential reasons, such as the ocean floor and the far side of the moon.

      Ecological considerations can also confer particular importance on mediated nature appreciation. Consider Sable Island: a remote sandy strip of land about 300 km off the eastern shore of Canada. It’s a striking landscape with a unique natural history and a fragile ecology: a 40-kilometer-long sandbar whose dunes, continually blasted by the winds of the North Atlantic, are held together by vegetation. Until recently, access to the island was restricted by the Canadian government, since trampling of the island’s native grasses poses a threat to dune stability and hence the very existence of the island. To the extent that anyone knew the beauty of the place at all, it was through photographs and films, such as those created in the 1990s by the photographer Roberto Dutesco, who obtained permission to visit the island and photograph its population of wild horses. In cases such as this, direct appreciation would come at a real environmental cost (for more on this case, see Parsons 2015).

      Philosophers on Meditated Nature Appreciation

      Over the last 50 years, there has been much philosophical discussion about various aspects of our practices of aesthetically appreciating nature. In these debates, some big differences have emerged, one of which concerns the role of scientific understanding in aesthetic appreciation. Some thinkers have insisted that the aesthetic appreciation of nature should be informed by our best understanding of nature and its history, just as our aesthetic appreciation of art must be informed by our best understanding of art and its history. The thought is that, just as to properly appreciate, say, a Cubist painting, one needs to understand the history and nature of that genre, so to appreciate a part of nature properly one needs the relevant historical and contextual knowledge about that part of nature. And such relevant historical and contextual knowledge about nature is to be found in our scientific understanding of it (Carlson 1979a). Others have rejected this requirement, eschewing any such normative constraint on nature appreciation. All that is needed to properly appreciate nature, some maintain, is careful attention and sensitivity to the features it displays in our perception of it: its striking forms and colors, its moving events, intriguing processes and so on.

      This division represents perhaps the main ideological split in the field (for a general discussion, see Parsons 2008; Carlson 2019). Despite this deep division, however, one thing that thinkers on both sides of the division share is a neglect of, if not contempt toward, mediated appreciation of nature.

      Consider first the leading representative of the view that nature appreciation should be informed by scientific understanding, Allen Carlson. Broaching the general question of how we ought to aesthetically appreciate nature, Carlson takes as his key insight the idea that nature is an environment. This means, in his view, that nature is not any particular object or set of objects before or around us, but rather the whole background setting in which we, and the objects around us, are enveloped. Thus, Carlson writes: “the beginning of an answer as to how to aesthetically appreciate an environment is something like the following. We must experience our background setting in all those ways in which we normally experience it, by sight, smell, touch and whatever” (1979a, 272).

      Having set up the idea of appreciating nature in this way, Carlson goes on to draw a strong contrast between this paradigm of direct sensory engagement of the environment and appreciation mediated by representations of nature, such as photographs. He writes:

      Carlson goes on to extend the same considerations to the related medium of landscape painting. His general conclusion, in our terminology, is that such representations are not appreciatively apt for natural environments.

      On the other side of the aforementioned ideological divide, we have writers such as Thomas Heyd, who rejects Carlson’s requirement that we bring scientific understanding to nature appreciation. We may, Heyd insists, instead draw on many different sorts of understanding in appreciation, including conceptions of nature to be found in fictional and literary works about the landscape, landscape painting, and mythological tales about nature from different cultures (2001).

Скачать книгу