The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method. Henri Poincare

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method - Henri Poincare страница 23

The Foundations of Science: Science and Hypothesis, The Value of Science, Science and Method - Henri  Poincare

Скачать книгу

a world enclosed in a great sphere and subject to the following laws:

      The temperature is not uniform; it is greatest at the center, and diminishes in proportion to the distance from the center, to sink to absolute zero when the sphere is reached in which this world is enclosed.

      To specify still more precisely the law in accordance with which this temperature varies: Let R be the radius of the limiting sphere; let r be the distance of the point considered from the center of this sphere. The absolute temperature shall be proportional to R2r2.

      I shall further suppose that, in this world, all bodies have the same coefficient of dilatation, so that the length of any rule is proportional to its absolute temperature.

      Finally, I shall suppose that a body transported from one point to another of different temperature is put immediately into thermal equilibrium with its new environment.

      Nothing in these hypotheses is contradictory or unimaginable.

      A movable object will then become smaller and smaller in proportion as it approaches the limit-sphere.

      Note first that, though this world is limited from the point of view of our ordinary geometry, it will appear infinite to its inhabitants.

      In fact, when these try to approach the limit-sphere, they cool off and become smaller and smaller. Therefore the steps they take are also smaller and smaller, so that they can never reach the limiting sphere.

      If, for us, geometry is only the study of the laws according to which rigid solids move, for these imaginary beings it will be the study of the laws of motion of solids distorted by the differences of temperature just spoken of.

      No doubt, in our world, natural solids likewise undergo variations of form and volume due to warming or cooling. But we neglect these variations in laying the foundations of geometry, because, besides their being very slight, they are irregular and consequently seem to us accidental.

      In our hypothetical world, this would no longer be the case, and these variations would follow regular and very simple laws.

      Moreover, the various solid pieces of which the bodies of its inhabitants would be composed would undergo the same variations of form and volume.

      I will make still another hypothesis; I will suppose light traverses media diversely refractive and such that the index of refraction is inversely proportional to R2r2. It is easy to see that, under these conditions, the rays of light would not be rectilinear, but circular.

      To justify what precedes, it remains for me to show that certain changes in the position of external objects can be corrected by correlative movements of the sentient beings inhabiting this imaginary world, and that in such a way as to restore the primitive aggregate of impressions experienced by these sentient beings.

      Suppose in fact that an object is displaced, undergoing deformation, not as a rigid solid, but as a solid subjected to unequal dilatations in exact conformity to the law of temperature above supposed. Permit me for brevity to call such a movement a non-Euclidean displacement.

      If a sentient being happens to be in the neighborhood, his impressions will be modified by the displacement of the object, but he can reestablish them by moving in a suitable manner. It suffices if finally the aggregate of the object and the sentient being, considered as forming a single body, has undergone one of those particular displacements I have just called non-Euclidean. This is possible if it be supposed that the limbs of these beings dilate according to the same law as the other bodies of the world they inhabit.

      Although from the point of view of our ordinary geometry there is a deformation of the bodies in this displacement and their various parts are no longer in the same relative position, nevertheless we shall see that the impressions of the sentient being have once more become the same.

      In fact, though the mutual distances of the various parts may have varied, yet the parts originally in contact are again in contact. Therefore the tactile impressions have not changed.

      On the other hand, taking into account the hypothesis made above in regard to the refraction and the curvature of the rays of light, the visual impressions will also have remained the same.

      These imaginary beings will therefore like ourselves be led to classify the phenomena they witness and to distinguish among them the 'changes of position' susceptible of correction by a correlative voluntary movement.

      If they construct a geometry, it will not be, as ours is, the study of the movements of our rigid solids; it will be the study of the changes of position which they will thus have distinguished and which are none other than the 'non-Euclidean displacements'; it will be non-Euclidean geometry.

      Thus beings like ourselves, educated in such a world, would not have the same geometry as ours.

      The World of Four Dimensions.—We can represent to ourselves a four-dimensional world just as well as a non-Euclidean.

      The sense of sight, even with a single eye, together with the muscular sensations relative to the movements of the eyeball, would suffice to teach us space of three dimensions.

      The images of external objects are painted on the retina, which is a two-dimensional canvas; they are perspectives.

      But, as eye and objects are movable, we see in succession various perspectives of the same body, taken from different points of view.

      At the same time, we find that the transition from one perspective to another is often accompanied by muscular sensations.

      If the transition from the perspective A to the perspective B, and that from the perspective to the perspective are accompanied by the same muscular sensations, we liken them one to the other as operations of the same nature.

      Studying then the laws according to which these operations combine, we recognize that they form a group, which has the same structure as that of the movements of rigid solids.

      Now, we have seen that it is from the properties of this group we have derived the notion of geometric space and that of three dimensions.

      We understand thus how the idea of a space of three dimensions could take birth from the pageant of these perspectives, though each of them is of only two dimensions, since they follow one another according to certain laws.

      Well, just as the perspective of a three-dimensional figure can be made on a plane, we can make that of a four-dimensional figure on a picture of three (or of two) dimensions. To a geometer this is only child's play.

      We can even take of the same figure several perspectives from several different points of view.

      We can easily represent to ourselves these perspectives, since they are of only three dimensions.

      Imagine that the various perspectives of the same object succeed one another, and that the transition from one to the other is accompanied by muscular sensations.

      We shall of course consider two of these transitions as two operations of the same nature when they are associated with the same muscular sensations.

      Nothing then prevents us from imagining that these operations combine according to any law we

Скачать книгу